Disclaimer: Clinical information is provided for educational purposes and not as a medical or professional service. Persons who are not medical professionals should have clinical information reviewed and interpreted or applied only by appropriate health professionals.
Ethicist
Introduction: Setting an Ethical Foundation
The ethical issue affecting the Watanabe family reflects an apparent conflict between the usual
American approach to bioethical decision making and the cultural values of the Watanabe family.
American bioethics is steeped in a tradition that emphasizes personal autonomy and patients'
rights along with the physician's duty to be beneficent and treat patients justly.
In particular, the principle of beneficence shapes the physician's duty to help patients, while the
principle of autonomy stems from the recognition that people have the unique capacity to make
reasoned choices and bear moral responsibility for their actions. These principles have important
implications for patient decision making. As the American Medical Association Council on
Ethical and Judicial Affairs states, "It is a fundamental ethical requirement that a physician
should at all times deal honestly and openly with patients. Patients have a right to know their
past and present medical status and to be free of any mistaken beliefs concerning their condition ...
Ethical responsibility includes informing patients of changes in their diagnoses resulting from
retrospective review of test results or any other information. This obligation holds even though
the patient's medical treatment or therapeutic options may not be altered by the new
information." The Council also wrote that, "The patient's right of self-decision can be
effectively exercised only if the patient possesses enough information to enable an intelligent
choice. The patient should make his or her own determination on treatment. The physician's
obligation is to present the medical facts accurately to the patient or to the individual responsible
for the patient's care and to make recommendations for management in accordance with good
medical practice. The physician has an ethical obligation to help the patient make choices from
among the therapeutic alternatives consistent with good medical practice."1
Thus we commonly assume that patients want to be informed and make choices that reflect their
values and priorities. In Mr. Watanabe's case, he cannot make an informed treatment choice
without knowing his diagnosis, yet his daughter is adamant that he not be told.
The Ethical Foundation of Informed Consent
Much of American bioethics is founded on the assumption that the physician's first obligation is
to the patient. Moreover, patients have the right to all relevant information and should be
encouraged to make their own "autonomous" treatment decisions. Our notion of informed
consent, or informed refusal, form the foundation for the doctor-patient relationship. The
President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and
Behavioral Research2 states that, "The ethical foundation of informed consent can be traced to
the promotion of two values; personal well-being and self-determination. To ensure that these
values are respected and enhanced, the commission finds that patients who have the capacity to
decide their care must be permitted to do so voluntarily and must have all relevant information
regarding their condition and alternative treatments, including possible benefits, risks, costs,
other consequences and significant uncertainties surrounding any of this information." Similar
positions are taken by the American Hospital Association in the Patient Bill of Rights3 and the
American College4 of Physicians Ethics Manual.5
The Elements of Informed Consent
In general, informed consent is a two-part process that includes disclosure by the health care
professional and the patient’s decision to either accept or decline the treatment. The elements of
informed consent include the information to be discussed, the patient's comprehension, the
patient's decisional capacity, and the voluntariness of the decision. The information to disclose
includes the nature of the intervention; the purpose of the intervention, including how any
knowledge gained from the procedure will change the treatment course or outcome; the risks of
the intervention including their severity and likelihood; the benefits of the proposed intervention;
and any alternative interventions, including what would happen without further treatment.
Consent forms provide written documentation of the patient's decision.
Throughout the discussion the doctor should assess the patient's comprehension. Frequently
asking the patient if he or she has questions is helpful for assessing the level of the patient's
understanding. If the doctor has any doubts about the patient's comprehension, the physician
should ask the patient to tell the doctor about the proposed treatment to assess the patient's
understanding. If the patient shows any confusion, the physician should review the issue in more
simple terms, consider involving a family member to help explain, and try to provide written
materials to supplement the discussion. So too, the physician must consider the patient's
decisional capacity. The physician must establish whether this patient can decide then. He
reminds Jean that, although the terms "decisional capacity" and "competency" are often used
interchangeably, competency involves a court determined assessment. In contrast, any
knowledgeable lay person can do an assessment of decisional capacity. If deciding whether a
patient has decisional capacity is difficult, the physician should consult with a psychiatrist,
neurologist, or similarly trained person with expertise in capacity assessment. The features of
decisional capacity include the ability to comprehend, possession of a value system, and the
ability to communicate. The decision must be made voluntarily, without coercion, manipulation,
deception or bribery.
How do these issues affect Mr. Watanabe's care?
In the Watanabe case, there is no question that Mr. Watanabe can comprehend the issue at hand,
nor is there any question about his capacity. Yet although he can decide, his daughter Jean
maintains that he would prefer not to know the details of his diagnosis. How then can Mr.
Watanabe make an informed choice about treatment options? Would delegating the decisions to
his daughter deprive him of his right to make plans about his future? Would withholding this
information from Mr. Watanabe be consistent with an ethical approach to patient care? How
does this reflect cultural differences and expectations? In short, how can the physician
beneficent toward Mr. Watanabe while respecting his autonomy?
Do doctors usually tell patients when the diagnosis is cancer?
Placing the issue of disclosure within an historical context is helpful. Over the past thirty years,
American physicians' disclosure practices have changed.6 In 1961, 90% of physicians favored
not telling patients they had cancer, but by 1979, 97% favored telling. This increase in the
number of physicians who tell patients about cancer can be attributed to many factors. Certainly
the patients' rights movement and the emphasis on patient autonomy have played a role. In
addition, physicians may fear malpractice suits for failure to disclose and for the patient's "lost
chance" to seek prompt treatment. Moreover, there is no support for the longstanding myth that
knowing the diagnosis is bad for the patient. In 1982 the President's Commission stated,
"There is very little empirical evidence to indicate whether and in what ways information can be
harmful. Not only is there no evidence of significant negative psychological consequences of
receiving information but, on the contrary, some strong evidence indicates that disclosure is
beneficial."7 Although physicians may withhold information from a patient whom they believe
would be directly harmed by the disclosure, this "therapeutic exception" is intended to be very
narrowly interpreted and time limited.
Yet we cannot simply assume that all patients must be well informed to make health care
decisions and to work in effective partnership with the physician. While the nature, purpose,
risks, benefits, and alternatives of a given treatment must be disclosed in terms the patient can
understand if we are to meet American standards for informed consent, the physician must
consider the patient's cultural background and expectations about health care decision making.
Must patients be informed, whether or not they desire the information? Are there different
cultural beliefs and expectations?
Some critics of bioethics have mistakenly concluded that the concept of patient autonomy
requires that patients make their own treatment decisions. This is a serious misconstrual of the
principle of autonomy. Patients may prefer to delegate decision-making authority to others and
may wish to remain uninformed about their own medical condition. Authorizing another to
decide is perfectly acceptable, provided the patient is making that choice freely. American
bioethics, although stemming from an emphasis on patient rights, recognizes the importance of
cultural values in decision making and the important web of relationships within which patients
make their choices. The key point is that the decision maker is chosen by the patient and that
choice can be changed by the patient anytime. As Pellegrino states, " ... autonomous patients
are free to use their autonomy as they see fit - even to delegate it when this fits their own concept
of beneficence ... To thrust the truth or the decision on a patient who expects to be buffered
against news of impending death is a gratuitous and harmful misinterpretation of the moral
foundations for respect for autonomy."8 The principle of autonomy remains universally valid
because it recognizes the unique qualities inherent in personhood. Its implementation across
cultures may differ, however, depending upon cultural values and expectations.
Cancer and Disclosure in Japan
In this case, Mr. Watanabe's cultural beliefs and values may be more consistent with traditional
Japanese approaches. We must recognize that the common understanding of informed consent
rests on a uniquely American foundation. In Japan, and in other countries, the decision about
whether to disclose to a patient a diagnosis of cancer is delegated to the patient's family
members, most of whom choose not to reveal the truth.9,10 While American physicians'
attitudes about disclosure have changed over the past thirty years, so that now most physicians
disclose diagnoses,11 the Japanese approach has not changed as much. Currently about 13% of
Japanese doctors inform cancer patients of their disease. Most doctors in Japan believe that
telling patients is cruel and can produce isolation and harm to family relationships. Moreover, in
Japanese culture there is a strong death taboo and emphasis on cure rather than palliative care.
The Japanese notion of what constitutes good patient care in the realm of disclosure of diagnoses
differs dramatically from our American concept, turning away from an approach that focuses on
patients' "rights."
Some compare the present Japanese practice surrounding truth disclosure to that of the United
States thirty years ago. Yet in a recent study, 60% of Japanese individuals surveyed said they
would want to be told the truth. Moreover, in 1989 the Japanese Ministry of Health and Welfare
recommended truth telling in cancer care.12 The four principles the group advocated talking into
account were 1) the aims of truth disclosure, 2) the ability of the patient and family to bear the
truth, 3) establishing a good relationship between health care workers and the patient and family
and 4) a commitment of health care workers throughout the management of the patient. The
expectations in Japan may be changing, yet a sizable minority of Japanese patients prefer not to
know their diagnosis, despite official recommendations.
Can a patient delegate informed decisionmaking to someone else?
The key point is that patients have the right not to know information if they prefer to have others
make informed choices for them. One cannot assume that values and expectations about decision
making in health care are universally shared. The challenge is to determine the patient's beliefs
and values and reconcile them with those of other family members and the health care providers.
The only way to be sure about how much involvement the patient wants is to ask the patient,
preferably before the time of a crisis. The doctor should have had this discussion with Mr.
Watanabe far earlier in their relationship. The physician should ask Mr. Watanabe if he prefers
to have someone else decide, and if so, whom. He should ask the limits that Mr. Watanabe
might want to impose on others' decision making authority, and how much information Mr.
Watanabe wants to have. Simply knowing that Mr. Watanabe is a member of a cultural group
that traditionally prefers not to know does not solve the problem, because the doctor does not
know whether this patient shares that cultural view.
How should caregivers approach patients?
One way to approach patients is to for the doctor to state that there are some important issues
regarding the patient's care to discuss, and then wait for the patient's response. If the patient
names an individual that the patient wants to serve as the decision maker, such as an eldest son,
then the physician should respect that choice by clarifying the situation with the patient,
documenting the situation in the patient's chart, and proceeding to work with the designated
decision maker. In addition, physicians need to recognize that knowing one's diagnosis and
prognosis is not an all or nothing phenomenon, and that a patient's knowledge level can vary
along a continuum. One approach to the patient is that of "offering truth"13 in which the
patient is offered the opportunity to become informed to whatever degree that patient wishes. In
that way, the information can be conveyed over time to the extent the patient is comfortable.
For Mr. Watanabe, there is no evidence that he "could not handle the news." Out of respect
for Mr. Watanabe's autonomy the physician must assume that he can handle the news unless
shown otherwise.14 However, physicians cannot overlook the concerns raised by the patient?s
family, and should consider that family a valuable resource. However, the doctor must remain
cognizant of the fact that the family's concerns may be shaped, in part, out of fear of loss. It is
only ascertaining the patient's true preferences that physicians can respect the patient's
autonomy in a meaningful way.
1. American Medical Association Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Code of Medical
ethics: Current Opinions and Annotations, Chicago: AMA, 1997. Pages 125, 120.
2. President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and
Behavioral Research, Washington, D.C.: The Commission, 1982.
3. American Hospital Association, "A Patient’s Bill of Rights", 1973.
4. American Medical Association Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Code of Medical
Ethics, 1996-1997 edition, page xli.
5. American College of Physicians Ethics Manual. Annals of Internal Medicine 1992; 117:947-
960.
6. Novack DH, Plumer R, Smith RL, Ochitill H. et. Al. Changes in physician’s attitudes toward
telling the cancer patient. JAMA 1979; 241(9):897-900.
7. President’s Commission for The Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and
Behavioral Research, Making Health Care Decisions, Volume 1, 1982.
8. Pelegrino ED. Is Truth Telling to the Patient a Cultural Artifact? In The Social Medicine
Reader, Duke University Press: Durham, North Carolina, 1997.
9. Uchitomi Y, Yamawaki S. Truth-telling practice in cancer care in Japan. Annals of New York
Academy of Sciences, 1997; 809:290-9.
10. Tanida N. Japanese Attitudes toward truth disclosure in cancer. Scand J Soc Med, 1994, vol
22(1):50-7.
11. Novack DH, Plumer R, Smith RL, Ochitill H, Morrow GR, Bennett JM. Changes in
physicians’ attitudes toward telling the cancer patient. JAMA 1979, 241:897-900.
12. Japanese Ministry of Health and Welfare and the Japan Medical Association. 1989. The
Report for Terminal Care. Chuo Hoki Shuppan, Tokyo. (In Japanese)
13. Freedman B. Offering truth: one ethical approach to the uninformed cancer patient. Arch
Intern Med, 1993, vol 153, 572-6.
14. Bok S. Lying: moral choice in public and private life. In Mappes T, Zembaty J. Biomedical
ethics, 3rd edition. New York: McGraw Hill, 1991.
Disclaimer: Clinical information is provided for educational purposes and not as a medical or professional service. Persons who are not medical professionals should have clinical information reviewed and interpreted or applied only by appropriate health professionals.